As noted in the May Freeman, American revolutionaries mixed classical-republican and liberal political languages somewhat indiscriminately. Republicanism posited a relation between power and property in which independent proprietors were the bulwark of liberty. English critics of post-1688 Whig mercantilism deployed republican ideas, leading many historians to paint them as “agrarians” resisting capitalism, modernization, and social change. (“Social change” routinely looms large when historians wish to discount human agency.)

John Taylor’s writings show how an anti-mercantilist critique could be a liberal critique, despite detailed agreement with more strictly republican analyses. His Inquiry (1814), for example, was a belated reply to John Adams’s Defence of the Constitution of Government of the United States (1787–88), in which Taylor explicitly rejected Adams’s archaic-republican “social balance” between legally entrenched social orders. For Taylor, even such republican terms as “corruption” and “virtue” had different meanings in the American context.

Each of three historical ages, Taylor writes, had its own artificial aristocracy. The newest was a financial oligarchy—England’s modern reality. American Federalists wanted it here. Oddly, he notes, colonial Americans had spotted abusive taxation more quickly than independent Americans did. Having managed to “explode . . . the antiquated social compact dogma,” they succumbed to “modern law charter dogma” protecting state-created property as eternally inviolable.

Taylor treats “those possessions as property, which are fairly gained by talents and industry, or are capable of subsisting, without taking property from others by law.” Absent church establishments and feudal dues, taxation was “the only engine for distributing and balancing property” and dividing society into “payers and receivers.” National debt, too, was a key engine of oppression, reflecting the wish “to anticipate the riches of posterity and bequeath it [our] misfortunes.”

Championing “labour” and “agriculture” against “paper feudalism,” Taylor’s class-conflict analysis highlighted the role of the state. In a world where numerous interests battened on the state, that analysis was an important tool. Taylor’s political sociology shares much with the French Restoration liberalism of J.-B. Say, Destutt de Tracy, Charles Comte, Charles Dunoyer, and Augustin Thierry.

Like Jefferson, Taylor was conversant, not just with English economists, but also with Say and Tracy. But Taylor has flashes of complete originality. After all, none (or few) of the French or English writers had looked hard at the rising American system, which they wrongly fancied was repudiating European mercantilism. Taylor was breaking new ground.

In Tyranny Unmasked (1822), written mainly against protective tariffs, Taylor carried forward his political class analysis with great sociological penetration. Taylor writes that no “property-transferring policy . . . can enrich” workers or merchants in general. A few of the latter gain by “becoming bankers, lenders to government, or factory owners.” Particular “mechanicks or agriculturists” might also profit: “A few individuals are enriched by every species of tyranny.”

Expanding, in Inquiry, on the contrast between true and false (state-created) property, Taylor observes: “Despotick power strives to blend itself with a legitimate government, as paper stock does with private property.” False property wrapped itself in the protective mantle of justly acquired property, and we must understand Federalist grumbling about “leveling” political tendencies in that light. Beneficiaries of mercantilist (re)distribution did not want their gains called into question. Finally, Taylor observes that in England, the financial aristocracy profits more from war than feudal aristocrats ever did, by gaining new fields for investment and by funding “the war which made the conquest.” Increased taxes to pay the interest were a further boon to this class.

Banking and “Paper Feudalism”

State-connected banking—the Bank of England and the Bank of the United States—was a primary target of Taylor’s political polemics. Here, a false analogy with everyday commercial borrowing confused matters. In Taylor’s view, paper stock and public debt are not necessary to commerce, even if, coincidentally, “they exist together in England.” That paper and debt were “the bane” of commerce could be “inferred from the necessity of England to resort to war and conquest to cultivate her commerce.” Paper bills were “signs or representations” of real things and a tax on monetary circulation. Taylor is happy that the American Revolution “succeeded” without establishing permanent public debt in lieu of paper currency. Revolutionary currency lost value, to be sure, but it did not linger on as an excuse for future taxation. It disappeared, having done only limited harm.

Banking, as practiced, was generally bad. The advantage of coin is the difficulty of multiplying it. Noting that under hard money, any supply of money is optimal, Taylor notices the banker’s “privilege” of keeping fractional reserves. With interest counting as assets, and multiple lendings of the same capital, massive transfers of real goods went forward. Again Taylor calls bank profits a “tax” paid to privileged corporations. Taylor’s conclusion? “The tyranny of fraud is not less oppressive than that of force.”

Taylor compares patronage gained by banking with that obtained by conquest. Where patronage “is obtained by foreign conquest, as in the acquisition of India by England, the people still suffer by the unconstitutional power it confers,” even though domestic patronage was directly “more calamitous.”

Taylor has a good grasp of international flows of money and goods—paper, specie, and commodities—and spots an illusion later central to Keynesian economic policy: “[A]n advancement of the price of labour, pari passu, would produce neither gain nor loss.” He observes that a paper-military-patronage aristocracy does without titles of nobility, but is no less dangerous for that. “Money and armies are the instruments of power,” he adds.

Everyday Class Conflict

Taylor believed that great extremes of wealth invariably sprang from extra-economic coercion and deceit. Here, he resembles that self-taught radical, Thomas Paine. Taylor sounds vaguely “Marxist,” while explaining why protectionism does not help English workingmen: “[I]t has established a monopoly which operates only in favour of their employers, increases the expenses of government, and feeds unproductive capital by sacrificing productive labour”—especially in agricultural and seafaring occupations, where the workers have “very little capital except their bodily labour.” Here is Marx’s labour-power category several decades early.

Taylor did not need to be a “proto-Marxist,” however, because liberals already possessed (but did not always employ) a theory of plunder (“spoliation”) featuring the state apparatus as the major cause of social conflict.

State Capitalism

State-promoted business enterprise was at the heart of everything Taylor opposed. Echoing James Harrington (1656), he writes that “enormous political power invariably accumulates enormous wealth, and enormous wealth invariably accumulates enormous political power.” Asserting the parasitic character of state-created capital, he denounced transfers of real wealth from the economically productive and the aggressive alliance of artificial capitalists, corrupt courtiers, and officials who profited on them.

Taxes raised to pay public debt drained resources away from productive uses, and public credit funded the standing army, an instrument of constitutional subversion and empire. America, Taylor complains, has followed England’s road to ruin, under Federalists and Republicans alike.

These considerations shed light on Jefferson’s frequent references to the need for “periodic revolutions.” Given the ills attending state-subsidized capitalism, the people must have room to undo state creation of wealth and classes. The Yazoo scandal comes readily to mind. Georgia lawmakers handed out millions of acres of western land to those who bribed them. When a later legislature undid the act, Chief Justice Marshall declared the grants a sacred trust under the federal contract clause, in a textbook example of English “charter law.”

Corporations

In Taylor’s day governments still chartered corporations as privileged monopolies for specific purposes “clothed” with a public interest. Taylor saw “hierarchy” (the established church) and “corporation” as “innately despotic,” since both were “appurtenances of sovereignty” and, therefore, “appurtenances of despotism,” because sovereignty “is indefinite.” Taylor’s insight seems ideally suited for understanding the triumph of American state capitalism, once we see that general incorporation laws in the Jacksonian Era left state-like corporate privileges intact while widening the base of privilege. (See Frank van Dun, “The Modern Business Corporation versus the Free Market?” Freeman, March 2003, pp. 29–33, and “Personal Freedom versus Corporate Liberties,” Philosophical Notes, No. 76, Libertarian Alliance [London], 2006, pp. 1–19.) The deep roots of American corporatism suggest Taylor’s relevance across most of American history.

War Finance

Taylor writes that debt financing renders a war “twice suffered; by the living, who supply all the expenses of war; by the unborn, who supply an equivalent sum, to take up certificates of the expenses. . . .” Debt issues had actually hampered the American Revolution, since “war carried on by paper, is starved by peculation, and produces the utmost degree of publick expense, with the least degree of publick spirit.” (Here Taylor anticipated several Austrian School economists.)

Taylor’s views on war and its financing deepened his critique of the presidency and centralization. The point of Taylor’s antimilitarism was to avoid the fate of “European nations,” which “exist for the benefit of armies and navies. . . .” War was “the keenest carving knife for cutting up nations into delicious morsels for parties and their leaders.” It “swells a few people to enormous size”; “puts arms into the hands of ambition, avarice, pride, and self-love”; and “breeds a race of men, nominally heroes, mistaken for patriots, and really tyrants.” Finally, party discipline gave 26 percent of the legislature—effectively controlling 51 percent—“the power of declaring war.” Alluding to dear old National Security, Taylor reminds us: “Conquests abroad are rare, and no compensation for conquest at home.”

Britain: The Negative Role Model

nless we uprooted subsidized capitalism, America would become England—with Whig oligarchy, class conflict, economic crises, taxes, standing army, constant war, and a confusion of state-created and privately earned property. Britain was our negative role model, whose chief evils—empire and domestic oppression—were intertwined. “Compulsion” guarded English commerce: England “is enriched, because labour is her slave; goaded by a paper system, and she makes competition shrink by a fleet.” Britain’s relative internal freedom was little comfort to its dependencies, as “nearly demonstrated in the relations between England and Ireland, and quite so in India.”

Empire, Monarchy, Oligarchy

England brings us—and Taylor—to the structural logic of empire. The English state was “a confederation of parties of interest,” excluding the people, and consisting of “the church of England, the paper stock party, the East India company, the military party, the pensioned and sinecure party, and the ins and outs, once called whigs and tories,” held together by the monarchy. The English nation “has no government,” and “no British nation” existed beyond these interest groups. Taylor notes that Samuel Johnson, “the best informed tory,” favored “a brisk circulation of money.” But “a brisk circulation of power is also produced,” and Dr. Johnson “neglected to tell us . . . that money attracts power, and power, money.”

Taylor’s works abound with examples of his realistic grasp of social interrelations. He addresses two common arguments for consolidated power: “uniformity of religion” and “the difficulty of governing an extensive territory.” Europe had given up the former, and America the latter (in terms of monarchy). Practical knowledge being widely dispersed in a large state, “moral geometry” limits the “knowledge and will” of a king. Hence, “beyond his orbit, monarchy ceases and some anomalous government ensues; oligarchical, military, deputy-royal, tumultuous, or infinitely variegated by circumstances” and “neither the virtues nor vices of a monarch are felt at a distance from his person.”

“Monarchy only succeeds,” Taylor says, in “armies, garrisons, savage tribes and private families.” The wider the sphere, the more a king has only a “power of changing oligarchs.” This brings Taylor back to patronage, dependent on “the very worst kind of oligarchs . . . irresponsible and unknown.” Here indeed was a government—neither republic nor monarchy. Where a republic and a monarchy each had the “power of distributing wealth,” the monarchy was less burdensome, “because it is less expensive to gratify the rapaciousness of one, than of many.”

Were America governed as a monarchy, it could “only retain the advantage of extensive territory, by an oligarchy composed of deputy-kings, bashaws, satraps or mandarins.” As a decentralized confederation of self-governing members, America might expand indefinitely, “forming a great nation, by a chain of republicks.” Here, Taylor sketches out the possibility of republican expansion, as opposed to Madison’s belief in expansion as necessity.

False republics, Taylor says, have “the heaviest taxes.” The American party system and presidential patronage bring forth oligarchy—and presidential power, war—spreading patronage and power economically and geographically. Here, domestic and foreign concerns are joined.

Republican Nonintervention

Where national security intrudes, Taylor yields little to “realist” necessities. We Americans can resist the European system “more successfully than any other nation.” America, “possessed of extensive territory, happily removed from real causes of collision with other nations . . . is peculiarly favoured by providence” for avoiding “the artifice of legal wars,” to which small nations succumb.

The Balance of Power

Taylor denied that the laws of nations conferred sovereignty on any American government. In agreement with many liberal thinkers, he doubted the “balance of power” principle. That doctrine fostered war by assuming inherent hostility between nations, and was thus “the most complete invention imaginable for involving one combination of states, in a war with another.” (Neither was Taylor impressed with the “balance of trade.”)

Within the union, the balance-of-power idea fared no better. After the Missouri Compromise, geographical blocs defined by slavery loomed. Balance-of-power politics implied tinkering and brokering outside the Constitution; and a sustained antislavery campaign against the South as a bloc, he wrote, “would certainly destroy the union.” Taylor foresaw “civil” war, with massive death and destruction. He makes the unkind aside that, “if our consciences tell us that we ought to enslave freemen, to make slaves free,” reformers might perhaps crusade in Brazil, Cuba, or Africa, rather than at home.

Slavery and Colonization

Taylor, who himself owned slaves, describes slavery as “an evil which the United States must look in the face. To whine over it, is cowardly; to aggravate it, criminal; and to forbear to alleviate it, because it cannot be wholly cured, foolish.” He hoped the slaves might “be gradually re-exported” through colonization—a point where he is no worse than his contemporaries and successors, including Abraham Lincoln. Taylor could be quite realistic about slavery. His frequent assertions that financial exploitation is worse than slavery cut both ways. In mitigation, he pleaded: “The profit extorted from the negro slave is moderated by the immediate interest of his master . . . the master’s benevolence and . . . respect for his own reputation.”

Although Taylor, like most of his contemporaries, believed whites were intellectually superior to blacks, he denied that this justified establishing privileged castes. Free use of “intelligence” improved church and state, and we should expect the same result with “labour.” He asks, “Are slaves free, because their labour is made more productive . . . by the intelligence of their masters? Is the white population of the world justified in converting to its own use the labour of Africa, on account of superiority of intellect?” The answer assumed is “no.”

Against Institutional Fixity

Taylor writes that “If a number of people should inclose themselves within a triangle, they would hear with great astonishment, that they had lost the power of changing the form of the inclosure; and that the dead form of the triangle governed living beings, instead of living beings who created that figure, governing it” (italics supplied).

Taylor is not abandoning law, institutions, or everyday morality. He does want to avoid being locked, beforehand, into eternally fixed political institutions, including the federal union. He was eager to discredit artificial intermediate institutions. As, in effect, a liberal methodological individualist, Taylor took the society he knew as given and spent little time on naturally existing intermediate institutions, which in his day remained intact.

Agrarianism and Economic Development

Literary historian M. E. Bradford sees Taylor as a defender of “closed, rural, religious, and corporate societies.” Such republics were not anti-commercial, but neither did they need the state as economic broker, promoter, and subsidizer. Taylor has of course some agrarian themes, but unlike Jefferson, he never asked to be on the literally isolated “footing of China.” Taylor’s society was already agrarian, and he hoped his political liberalism (called “republicanism”) would, in a decentralized federation, allow agrarian communities to flourish.

Some might suppose that Taylor’s ideas would, in practice, have blocked American economic growth. Writing of the English Enclosures, French historian Paul Mantoux comments that if “the bulk of the rural population remained on the land, the triumph of the factory system might have come later, but it could not have been indefinitely postponed.” This suggests that “modernization” under republican liberalism was feasible enough, and that such modernization might have been slower, more organic, and less chaotic than the state-dependent path actually taken. (The federal center long set a bad example of providing wars for the “primitive accumulation” of Indian lands, making it unlikely that a market economy without massive state assistance would ever enjoy long-lasting political popularity.)

The Continuing Relevance of John Taylor

Taylor summed up his outlook as follows: “Our policy divides power, and unites the nation in one interest; Mr. Adams’s divides a nation into several interests and unites power.” For a brief period after his death, Taylor became a prophet for hard-money, free-trade advocates in the wider Jacksonian movement.

Taylor’s work did not have the effect for which he hoped, but it has its merits as a critical benchmark by which to measure what has happened to the Old Republic. In Taylor’s opinion, artificial aristocrats can only sustain their projects in the long run through some form of political despotism—consolidation, empire, or monarchy. These outcomes are all around us, and John T. Flynn could repeat all of Taylor’s themes in the 1940s and early ’50s. As historian J. G. A. Pocock writes, “America may have guaranteed the survival of the forms of corruption it was created to resist.” We cannot say that John Taylor failed to warn us.